Though Charles Taylor never
confesses to a particular ethical framework or moral source for the making of
an (moral) identity, his particular style of writing and unarticulated beliefs
seem barely apparent to me. I believe that he has a tremendous respect for the
philosophical and theological writings of Augustine. I will make an effort to bring them together
for similarities in their understanding of the moral self and moral sources. For Taylor , he believes that the framework of
self-mastery through reason (one of many moral frameworks), has theistic
variants in Jewish and Christian thought and the change has come about as the
work of grace. For Augustine, everything that the moral being is possesses the
gift of grace including the will. Augustine believes that virtues depend on
right and rational choices. In Augustine’s description of the will, it had a
central position in every ethical action, inclusive of the virtues of justice,
prudence, self-control and courage.
However, the will must have a
certain direction as distinctions of higher and lower in terms of altruism and
selfishness has come to the fore. Augustine agrees with the Stoics of his time
more than the Epicureans that happiness comes not from the pleasure of the body
but from the pleasure of the mind. Virtue of the mind is a necessary condition
for happiness, which is a gift of God and not an achievement of human
achievement. As we strive for happiness in the afterlife, God has also made the
world for our aesthetic pleasure in our accomplishments in science, music, art
and literature. The two types of value that Augustine asserts are intrinsic and
values that we assign for purposes of utility.
Humans have intrinsic value and the virtuous person would never regard
it as merely the means to his own end. Christ’s command for us to love one
another prohibits the value of utility to another person. We love people
because they belong to God and not to us. Our value is never independent of
God, as he is the creator of us, nature and all things. Virtue for Augustine is
rightly ordered love, rooted in charity and the love of God; for virtue is not
the product of natural aptitude, sound upbringing or individual human effort.
In loving God, we naturally love ourselves and there is no need for a third
commandment of love. Loving ourselves is as natural as breathing and likewise
there is no commandment to breathe.
As Taylor speaks about moral and spiritual
intuitions as we articulate our moral being, he uses the term strong
evaluations that describe discriminations of right or wrong, better or worse
and higher and lower as they relate to issues of justice, dignity and respect
for other people’s lives. This accountability of our intuition is often
described as inarticulate, as Taylor
understands the ethics of inarticulacy. Taylor
prefers to think that our moral reactions are more than instincts, but also an
assent to an affirmation of a given ontology of the human. Augustine says that
the grace of God gives illumination to what is right and additional assistance
when needed to improve the control and understanding of the will. Only grace
can restore authentic freedom and that of the will.
Augustine sees moral philosophy as an enquiry
into the supreme good and how we can attain it; in this sense, he is a
Platonist. One seeks happiness for one s own sake and not as an end to some
other means. He was no different than other philosopher of his own period and
it was not necessarily a distinctive Christian view. For him, it was also the
art of living. Attaining material goods and wealth in this life to achieve
happiness is not necessarily undesirable, but one must not love it. One must be
aware of falling in love with objects unworthy of love. Happiness is finding
the truth and knowledge and to do this. One must live as God lives and that our
mind and reason should be subjected to God. Faith is prior to our understanding of God,
yet our understanding remains a matter of reasoning and philosophical inference
Taylor would
understand this as one of many moral frameworks, and that of Christianity. Jesus
Christ, the incarnation of God, without whom, no human being could ever succeed
in being happy and this happiness lies in immortality. As Taylor approaches the value and nature of
goodness, he believes that modern moral philosophy has tended to focus on what
it is right to do rather than the nature of what it is good to be. Here, one
finds a particular type of resonance between the two.
As Augustine was a follower of
Plato through Plotnius, he understands the ideals of the eternal against the
temporal and the immutable against the ever-changing. The platonic idea of the
Good is foundational for Augustinian’s Goodness of God, His thoughts, His Word,
His order, His Ideas, His eternal law and our participation in it. As we
observe these spiritualities, we must then turn the attention of our desires
and our will to God so that our will is absorbed into the Goodness of God. For Taylor , we participate in
dialogue with others, the universe and God as we discover our moral lives. We
narrate our lives as we travel upwardly to attain meta values and eventually
the hyper-value and inwardly to discover our inner being and nature.
Turning and direction are very
important for Plato and Augustine because the direction of the gaze is the
decisive element. It is the gift of God’s love and not concupiscence that
assists us to do this. This is a dialogical approach in our relationship with
God that helps us to attain to this Goodness. Taylor would agree that we can only know
ourselves and have a direction to this higher Good and by having consistent and
narrative moments in our lives as we progress through life. He also posits an
inner and an outer in his approach to understanding the nature of existence and
understanding of the soul which he sees as the inner. The understanding of this
basic difference between the outer and the inner is that the inner is that
sense, our spiritual purpose for going from the lower to the higher which is
the road to God. Plato differs from Augustine in that God is out there with the
externals, but for Augustine, God is in us as an inner light guiding the way
and to knowing God. God is found in the activity of “knowing itself”, as
opposed to the objects known.
Turning towards our inner self and
the light within us is described as reflexive, also meaning that we should take
more care of the inner than the outer. Here we take the first- person
standpoint. Even though Taylor engages more of the second-person, dialogical
approach, in understanding the self and knowing God, Augustine and Taylor both
agree that the “experiencing itself” has value more-so than the objects
experienced. Awareness takes on a different meaning and value when the agent
himself is aware that he is aware. To understand the presence of one’s self in
the world is very important for Augustine and reflexivity brings us closer to
God. It is important to note that this reflexivity that comes with turning
inwards is a personal and immediate and founded in the first-person standpoint.
Taylor has an
interest in the modern identity. He believes that there is an array of
understandings of what it is to be a human agent, including senses of
awareness, freedom, and individuality; humans are fit objects of respect and
have immunity. His understanding of the ethics of inarticulacy announces that
we have many inarticulate understandings of the moral self.
The modern identity for Taylor has
three major facets, “modern inwardness, the sense of ourselves as beings with
inner depths, and the connected notion that we are “selves”; second, the
affirmation of ordinary life which develops from the early modern period;
third, the expressivist notion of nature as an inner moral source”. He also
conjectures three axes in moral thinking; our sense of respect for and
obligations to others, our understandings of what makes a full life and the
range of notions that deal with dignity. As these facets and axes in moral
thinking form a framework, no framework is shared by everyone; and not having a
framework is to fall into a life which is spiritually senseless. There is a
relationship between self and morals in the modern identity and understanding
of the self. This modern identity is richer in moral sources, but this richness
is often made invisible by philosophical languages.
The natural susceptibility to feel
sympathy for others is more than the consequence of upbringing and education as
we have moral concerns for the respect of life, integrity, well being and
flourishing of others. Moral reactions are also more than gut reactions or
socio-biologically explained. We are all
universalists in our moral descriptions and moral reactions as we consider the
ontological nature of human beings, i.e. something grounded in the nature of
being as he notes that there is a great deal of motivated suppression for moral
ontology by contemporaries for various reasons and especially from modern
epistemology..
No comments:
Post a Comment